Debussy, Wolpe and Dialectical Form
Matthew Greenbaum
It is hard to imagine music more dissimilar
than that of Claude Debussy and Stefan Wolpe. And yet Wolpe's approach to form
owes a great deal to Debussy, who - as I will try to show - first elaborated
the dialectical scheme so common in Wolpe. By examining the historical
evolution of this hitherto unlabelled form we can better understand Wolpe's
indebtedness. We shall use as illustrations a preliminary example from Don Giovanni, then
Debussy's "Des pas sur la neige" and finally Wolpe's Form for piano.
In the most rudimentary dialectical form a
musical idea progressively generates its antithesis: a gradually emerging
contradictory idea. (1) Conflict, contrast, and opposition:
all are types of antithesis. Just as other aspects of music, antithesis also
had a historical development, which culminated in new form-generating
structures in late-19th century music, as I will try to demonstrate below. This
was a result of the increasingly subjective musical aesthetic that was to find
its full flowering in Symbolism and which required a new vehicle of
representation once it had transcended the structural and representational
confines of common practice tonality.
While a work like "Des pas sur le
neige" can be analyzed in many ways - the most inviting being, perhaps, a
modified strophic structure or rounded binary form - these descriptions do not
account for its evolutionary dynamic. I maintain that its underlying
dialectical process is powerful enough to reduce details of formal repetition
to epiphenomena; or rather, that the dialectical process appears to produce
form as it moves through time. Even though one may bridle at the use of the
word 'form' to describe what at first might appear to be only a process, the
totalizing effects of this process are impossible to ignore.
You may have assumed that Hegelian logic is
the source of this dialectical thinking; but it is difficult to determine the
direction of influence as far as Hegel and his musical contemporaries were
concerned. Beethoven owned a few of Hegel's works although it is unclear to
what extent he made use of them. (2) In fact, Beethoven and Hegel both
drew upon conventions of musical rhetoric which themselves originated in the
classical tropes. (3)
The Enlightenment organicism of Kant and
Goethe valued artworks that developed from a motivic kernel, and which seemed
to be driven by an inner necessity comparable to a biological process. No
detail should be extraneous to the cellular growth of the whole. Beethoven is
heir to this aesthetic. It would seem, then, that the organicist model left no
room at all for self-contradiction. But contradiction had already entered music
with the classical rhetorical figures, which had permeated the logic of Baroque
music as oratorical tropes and which persisted through the Classical Period.
The Baroque fully embraced Aristotle's
definition of rhetoric as a counterpart of dialectic (disputation). The
enthymeme, or rhetorical demonstration, (4) underlay
the Affekten;
contradiction in music was meant to exert the same oratorical force as rebuttal
in debate, but whose object now was the listener's submission to an Affekt
rather than to an argument.
This is borne out in Baroque music theory.
According to Mattheson, the main idea (Propositio)
is to be succeeded by one or more counter-statements (Propositio variate) at last
opposed by the Confutatio,
or resolution of objections "expressed by ... the citation and refutation
of apparently foreign passages. ... Everything that goes against the
proposition is resolved and settled." (5)
Affirming this redendes Prinzip - the "speaking"
or "oratorical" principle in music - Riepel writes, in analogy to the
rhetoric of exegesis: "A preacher cannot constantly repeat the Gospel and
read it over and over; instead, he must interpret it. ... In addition to the
thesis [Satz],
he has at the very least an antithesis [Gegensatz]." (6)
These terms were given to the themes of the sonata movement a generation later
by Forkel (1788), who calls the main theme the Hauptsatz [thesis] and the contrasting
theme the Gegensatz
[antithesis]. (7)
All this antedates Hegel, who, in the Vorlesungen über die
Äesthetik (1820 - 1829) uses similar language to describe
musical contrast. (8) Borrowing Riepel's terms, Hegel sees
thematic contrast as a contradiction (Gegensatz).
Most comprehensively Hegel describes the antithesis (Gegensatz) of consonance
and dissonance as a conflict between imaginative freedom and the necessity of
an underlying harmonic logic. (9) It is in the Äesthetik that Hegel
links the principal of rhetorical conflict with an overarching metaphysics of
time and consciousness.
The naturalism of the Enlightenment had
streamlined the relationship between form and content: the "public"
nature of the late-18th century sonata required that the affective intention
must be grasped immediately along with the form. (Indeed, the dialectic of
tonic and dominant - a closed circle of distance and return - is a rhetorical
figure in itself.) Themes were character types, essentially interchangeable
with operatic figures. The aim was the depiction of human nature; or, rather,
nature in its human dimension. The Kantian sublime was new to this schema,
although the harbinger of things to come.
The representation of the sublime, which
includes everything terrifying and otherworldly, required the employment of
contemporary outer limits of tonality: sequences of diminished seventh chords,
functional chromaticism and modulatory sequences. In Don Giovanni Mozart begins
to press beyond these conventions. Consider the following curious moment, where
the ghostly statue of the Commandatore is about to drag the Don to Hell:
Example 1: From Mozart: Don
Giovanni
The distinctiveness of this passage is the
result of rather startling chromatic and whole-tone implications, brought into
relief by octaves with no explanatory harmonies to support them. Note the:
-
0148 tetrachord (at A).
-
chromatic accumulation in the voice part at B
-
subsequent orchestral scalar figure at A', which completes the 12-tone
aggregate, as does the chromatic bass movement A'').
-
the implied descending whole-tone sequence at C, which also includes a C#/F
dyad at D whose harmonic logic is nearly impossible to grasp by ear.
In the dialectic of Don Giovanni, the carnal
world of the earthly characters emerges from a supernatural world first
enunciated in the overture and concluding in the spirit-ridden scene where the
Don meets his perdition. (The work originally ended here, nicely resolving the metaphysical
conflict, but this solution was considered insufficiently moralistic, impelling
Mozart to add a final sextet). As a result of a new arsenal of compositional
innovations, music vastly expanded its capacity to represent the subjective.
Modulation to heretofore inaccessible key areas (thanks to equal temperament),
Lisztian octatonicism, whole-tone scale expansions of the French sixth chord,
extended chromaticism; all permitted the depiction of novel psychological
worlds. Coinciding with - and indeed linked with - the Symbolist movement, this
panoply of devices allowed the pictorialization of transcendent, infinitely
subtle psychological states. The character contrast of sonata form was subsumed
into metaphysical opposition. The extension, or even abolition, of tonal
conventions offered the possibility of a form based entirely on the generation
of contradiction. The replacement of tonality by other scalar forms and
extended chromaticism, as in Liszt and Debussy, demanded a dialectical logic to
avoid a discontinuous, "inorganic" partitioning of unrelated
materials. But this form required a rhetoric of imagery to make it comprehensible:
the imagery of Symbolism.
Hegel had already made a connection between
musical logic and the symbolic. He describes the logic of instrumental music as
a representation (Vorstellung)
of abstract feelings (abstraktere
Empfindungen) (10); but also as ready to
represent the most varied meanings; a correspondence with the inner self of the
listener who must quickly decode (entziffern)
and grasp its symbolic (symbolisch)
meaning. (11)
Given
our limitations of space it must be pointed out only in passing that it was
Wagner who first made music out of this new rhetoric of symbols. Baudelaire,
whose sonnet "Correspondances" was the exemplar of Symbolism, was a
passionate Wagnerite. (12)
The
Ring
can be understood as a vast dialectic in which the world of the gods and men
emerges from Nature, i.e., the Rhine, only to plunge back in a final cataclysm. (13)
This grand metaphysic is reflected in the basic level of character conflict and
its musical analog, the Leitmotif.
It was Debussy, however, who perfected a
dialectical form without words. Here, he followed Liszt, whose Nuages gris is a daring -
if rather modular - example of the form. The music of Debussy is less a
discourse, in the 18th century sense, than a sounding correspondence with the
natural world. (14) Here, the redendes Prinzip - music
as discourse - has been overshadowed by a new sense of music as object, as a process
resonating with the natural world: organicism enriched by Symbolism.
A "symbolic" music must stand in
opposition to developing variation and other conventional techniques of
development since symbols, sound-symbols included - must be taken in as a
sensuous whole at the moment of their occurrence. Conventional development
would destroy their meaning; they can only emerge and disappear.
"Des pas sur la neige..." (Préludes I #6) is a
completely realized dialectical form. (15) It
evolves from the interpenetration of disparate pitch materials (diatonic,
octatonic, whole-tone and chromatic). Its brief apotheosis, an
"organum" in the G diatonic pitch collection, emerges from this
matrix and stands in dramatic opposition to the prelude's initial D modal minor
tonality. (16)
Example 2 illustrates the emergent process in
"Des pas sur la neige". Pitches in the D minor collection are
represented by diamond-shaped noteheads while normal noteheads represent the
emergent G major collection (overlapping pitches E - enharmonic F, and B
diamond-shaped). The whole-tone and octatonic collections, which mediate
between the D and G collections, are indicated by dotted shapes; the former by
dotted circles and the latter by rectangles.
The point of emergence in "Des pas sur
la neige" is signaled by a brief halt in the D E F ostinato figure that
runs through the rest of the prelude. The pitches of this ostinato are shared
by the D minor, whole tone and octatonic collections. This permits a constant
reinterpretation of the figure, as if it were moving through a gradually
changing physical space. (17)
Example 2:
Debussy; Des pas sur la
neige, Pitch Collection Analysis
Diamond noteheads indicate D minor collection. Normal
noteheads indicate G major collection.
Whole-tone collections are indicated by dotted curves and
octatonic collections by dotted rectangles.
The whole-tone set shares three pitches each with
the D minor and G major collections, allowing it to function as a pivot-an
extended French sixth (F# C B D and then E) in mm. 8 to 10 - in relation to the
preceding D minor region as well as the succeeding (enharmonically-spelled) D
dominant seventh chord. This harmony recurs in measures 14 and 15 and again in
m. 23, finally to be resolved in the emergence of the G area in measures 29
through 31.
Example
2 shows the gradual submersion of the D collection and the reciprocal emergence
of the G collection. (18) The intervals of the ostinato
comprise the basic cell of the octatonic collection [013], and it is therefore
not surprising that octatonicism plays an integrative role in the prelude,
where it aids the transformation of the D into the G (19)
Figure 1: Overlapping sets in "Des pas sur la neige"
An
additional aspect of organization in the prelude, one that enhances the
ambiguity of the pitch collections, is the reordering of repeated material.
This technique plays a similar role in Wolpe's Form for Piano, as shown in Martin Brody's
"Sensibility Defined: Set Projection in Stefan Wolpe's Form for piano" (20),
where Brody describes the migration of what Wolpe calls "autonomous
fragments." Although these fragments are sometimes no larger than a single
interval, their irregular patterns of repetition have a mnemonic function
similar to reordered measures in Debussy.
Mm. 3 and 19 in "Des pas sur la
neige" are nearly identical, and mm. 5 and 20 are completely so. But the
logic of source measures 3 to 5 is broken by the omission of the intermediary
m. 4: there is no duplicate m. 4 separating m. 19 from m. 20. Such telescoping
makes it difficult to recall the original order of materials. This stands in
stark contrast to conventional tonal forms, which depend on strict succession and
literal repetition to support recollection and comparison. The technique of
fugitive retrospection in "Des pas sur la neige" is suggestive of the
Symbolist aesthetic of transcendence that sought trans-temporal
"recollections" of prior existences throughout painting and poetry.
Dialectical
form pervades 20th century music. Elliott Carter speaks of his own 'epiphanic
form' and articulates a lineage with Debussy and Schoenberg. In Carter's
'epiphanic form,'
...
the relations between musical ideas are revealed non-linearly across a piece
rather than in the
form
of theme and variation or development. The term 'epiphany' was adopted by James
Joyce
to
mean the sudden revelation of meaning; ... Carter points to Schoenberg's Erwartung and to
Debussy's
Jeux as musical
precedents for this technique. (21)
Carter might have added Stravinsky to his
list; examples abound: Symphonies
of Wind Instruments (1920, rev. 1947) is a case in point. It originated
as a chorale for piano in memory of Debussy. Stravinsky made the chorale serve
as the conclusion to the wind piece and composed the rest of the work to lead
up to it. The chorale is foreshadowed a number of times before its emergence.
A dialectic of emergence is at work in much
of Schoenberg's music. The Serenade
op. 24 - a direct predecessor of 12-tone composition - is a case in point. The
motif of the parodistic first section of the Tanzscene
movement is a hexachord whose symmetrical complement is the thematic basis of
the movement's more lyrical trio sections. (22)
Hexachordal opposition produces a polarity in the fabric of the work.
Schoenberg was to make use of this polarity - to a greater or lesser degree -
in all subsequent hexachordal compositions. Here, the emergent moment is
replaced by an oscillation between complementary hexachords. Wolpe extended
this idea to include an oscillation between two unequal or asymmetrical pitch
collections, as in the second movement of Piece
in Two Parts for flute and piano and Form for piano.
Stefan Wolpe's long friendship with
Varèse reinforced his early predilection for dialectical thinking. Many
of Wolpe's works - particularly the late music - must be understood in this
perspective. (23) Both Wolpe and Varèse posited a musical
space that acts as a field for pitch structure. (24)
Varèse's works (and Wolpe's from Form
for piano and after) are made up of assemblings and dispersals of pitch
symmetries that underlie and motivate such structures, generating a total form
that Varèse describes as analogous to the growth of crystals. (25)
Here, the dialectical opposition is a series of contradictions, the totality of
which is the form of the work.
Austin Clarkson, speaking of Wolpe's notion
of fantasy, quotes Karl Jung's distinction between 'symbol' and 'sign', where a
sign stands for a "known thing" while a symbol "formulates an
essential unconscious factor." (26) Wolpe
not only drew upon Debussy's formal innovations, but also, surprisingly, his
art of fashioning symbol-laden musical ideas as well.
Clarkson describes Form for piano as a series
of "forty or so images." He goes on to say that
The
forces needed to make so many different items cohere are generated not from
familiar
rhetorical strategies of exposition, complication, crisis, and release, but from
the ten-
sions
generated from the juxtaposition of strongly contrasted images. (27)
Wolpe suggests this in
his notes to Form
for piano, as well as verifying its dialectical basis, when he writes:
Since
opposites become adjacencies, the modes of opposite expression as hard and
soft, wild
and
tame, flowing and hesitant, etc., all these modes become self-inclusive. The
piece feeds its
own
totality and brings everything into its focus. (28)
The
"thesis" of Wolpe's Form
for piano is self-evident; it is the hexachordal monody that begins the piece
(see Example 3). Its antithesis is the complementary hexachord in m. 4. The
dialectical unfolding and interpenetration of these two hexachords eventually
generates their
transpositions, which emerge at just before the midpoint of the piece at m. 30
and then dominate it until m. 58, as shown in Figure 2. The emergence of the
transpositions is the dialectical core of the work.
I shall borrow Brody's nomenclature and call
hexachord I, "P"; its transposition is T5P. Hexachord II is called Q
and its transposition is T5Q. In Figure 2 P is indicated with black noteheads
and Q with white. Transpositions are indicated with small noteheads. This makes
clear the interpenetration of the hexachords and the emergence of the
transpositions. Pushing Debussy's principle of non-repetition even farther, no
measures - or even symmetries - are repeated literally.
Although P and Q are equally well-represented
in Form, P is
granted special status; it makes up the opening monody and its two successive
variants, and is repeated just before the end in MM. 59 to 61; an octave lower
and with varied attack patterns, but still recognizable as a thematic idea. Q,
however, functions as the "Other"; the antithetical content into
which P continually dissolves. Clarkson, paraphrasing Wolpe, describes each
hexachord with a compound image: the first as "inward, centering,
compressing, and contracting" while the second "expands, rarifies,
unfocuses, and releases."
Two
principles govern the structure of Form.
The first is the interpenetration of hexachords; the second is the disposition
of symmetrical relations between them. Where these groups appear alone there
tend to be fewer symmetries and very little polyphony (as in MM. 1-3, 5,
the first half of 6, 11-12 or 60-64.) When they interpenetrate, a web of
symmetries appears, often spanning the entire range of the passage from the
highest to the lowest pitch, as in MM. 28 and 51.
Example 3 :
Wolpe Form, opening page
© Tonos Editions, distr. Seesaw Music 2067 Broadway
Ave, NYC
Figure 2: Wolpe: Form, Hexachodal Analysis:
Boxes and brackets mark symmetries. Dotted boxes show dotted symmetries.
Intervals of symmetry is sometimes indicated for clarity. Whlte noteheads:
Hexachord P. Black noteheads: Hexachord Q. Small noteheads: transpositions.
These
symmetrical progressions are dynamic; they result from the projection of intervals
from register to register. Such interval likenesses create the spatial
dimensionality so characteristic of Wolpe's music. The projected intervals
operate in the manner of rhymes which link together dissimilar ideas and
project a poem forward in time. Figure 2 shows symmetries as boxed pitch groups
or as bracketed pitches connected by dotted lines. Dotted boxes show additional
symmetries. Hexachord mixtures tend to present the greatest symmetrical
content, as in mm. 14-15, 27, and particularly 28.
The interaction
of symmetries is the dialectic of Form
for piano. As Example 3 shows, there is very little music that escapes these
symmetrical relationships, which must have been sketched out first in what
Wolpe called "precompositional selectivity." Pitches that do not
sound in vertical symmetries are nearly always part of a horizontal symmetry,
as the G and A in m. 4, which, together with the E F#, are in symmetrical
opposition to the D C in the same measure. More than simply reiterating an
interval, the G and A from hexachord P are projected onto kindred intervals in
the suddenly emerging hexachord Q in dialectical forward motion.
There are
four basic dialectical tropes in Form::
Emergence:
of hexachord T5P and T5Q
Interpenetration:
here, the hexachordal process
Transformation:
the recomposition of hexachords, as in the reworkings of P in mm.1-4
Symmetry
As we
have seen, the first three are also characteristic of "Des pas sur la
neige". It is here that that the kinship between Wolpe and Debussy visibly
emerges. While symmetry plays no obvious role in Debussy, it is worth noting
that the whole tone, octatonic and pentatonic collections are symmetrical, as
are many of their subsets, and this colors the pitch language of "Des pas
sur la neige". The above categories are not meant to be exhaustive - many
others are possible - but are offered as a first step in the creation of a new
analytic instrument.
The
notion of dialectical form permits us to think about post-tonal music in an
active mode. Viewed from this perspective, each event in a work so constructed
bears a meaningful and dynamic relationship to the process of emergence that
governs it, rather than simply manifesting a series of "one thing after
another" that Wolpe parodies in "Thinking Twice" (29) and
often dismissed as a "mittler Zustand Extase" (average-state
ecstasy).
Wolpe
delighted in teaching "Des pas sur la neige". It must be admitted
that no Wolpe sound surface resembles it, Form
for piano least of all. That composers as dissimilar as Wolpe and Debussy could
have shared a common understanding of musical form- as well as a kinship
relation as far as musical imagery is concerned - is evidence of a broader
historical process that embraced them both.
1. There are also extended types of
dialectical form: a rondo-like succession of syntheses (as in the emergent
moments of Debussy's "La Cathedrale engloutie"; or a continuous
series of momentary syntheses, as in works of Edgard Varèse and Stefan
Wolpe. See Greenbaum, "The Proportions of Density 21.5: Wolpean Symmetries
in the Music of Edgard Varèse" in On the Music of
Stefan Wolpe,
Austin Clarkson, ed., Pendragon (Hillsdale, New York: 2003) 207-219.
2.
David
B. Dennis, "Beethoven at large: reception in literature, the arts,
philosophy, and politics" in The
Cambridge Companion to Beethoven, Glenn Stanley, ed., Cambridge U
Press (Cambridge: 2000) 300. Beethoven's motivic unity over multiple-movement
compositions, as well as his use of cyclical forms, are suggestive of
dialectical thinking.
3.
The
Frankfort School post-Hegelian Theodor Adorno understood the Beethoven's
late-period style as a dialectic between the subjective and objective which
embodied a fatalistic reaction to the failure of political ideals. More to the
point, he understood exposition/development/ recapitulation in Beethoven's
middle period style as embodying the thesis/antithesis and integration of the
dialectic. See Rose Rosengard Subotnik, "Adorno's Diagnosis of Beethoven's
Late Style: Early Symptoms of a Fatal Condition," JAMS 29, 1976 242-275. A
rather simplistic dialectical-materialist approach to Beethoven and Hegel can
be found in Ballantine C., "Beethoven, Hegel and Marx" in Music Review 33, 1972, pp.
34-7.
Philip T.
Barford ("Beethoven and Hegel," Musica
1953, 437-440) has pointed out that the tension between
subjectivity and objectivity in Beethoven's sonata forms is precisely that of
Hegel's understanding of music in the Aesthetik.
4.
The
Art of Rhetoric,
trans. H. C. Lawson-Tancred. Penguin (London: 1991) 68.
5.
Hans
Lenneberg, "Johann Mattheson on Affect and Rhetoric in Music (II)," Journal of Music Theory
119-236. 195.
6.
Hans
Lenneberg, "Johann Mattheson on Affect and Rhetoric in Music (II)," Journal of Music Theory
119-236. 195.
7.
Riepel,
Anfangsgründe zur musikalischen Setzkunst 1752; quoted in Mark Evan Bonds,
Wordless Rhetoric: Musical
Form and the Metaphor of the Oration Harvard University Press
(Cambridge and London: 1991) 99.
8.
Bonds
124.
9.
E.g.,
" ... such progressions and modulations ... which require none too violent
antitheses [Gegensätzen]
... Rather, a satisfactory unity [Einheit] is produced." Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,
Vorlesungen über die Äesthetik III: Works: 15. Surhrkamp
(Frankfurt am Main: 1970) Hegel 187.
10.
Hegel
188-189.
11.
Hegel
217.
12.
"Correspondances
[in Les Fleurs du Mal]
... became the gospel of the new poetic movement. The language of Baudelaire
appeals as much to the intellect of the reader as to his physical
sensibilities. It does not directly represent things and feelings; it offers a
choice of the most suggestive correspondences among analogies which exist
between words, and sounds and their atmosphere-a choice which tends to create a
harmonious poetic substance which acts upon the imagination, not only through
its meaning, but also through its sound." Stefan Jarocinski, Debussy:
Impressionism and Symbolism, Rollo Myers trans. Eulenberg Books (London: 1976)
65.
13.
Wagner
speaks of Hegel only in connection with his metaphysics; Hegel was replaced,
first by Feuerbach and then Schopenhauer, in his philosophical development. See
Bryan Magee, The Tristan
Chord, Metropolitan Books (NY: 2000) 134 and passim.
14.
It
is no longer "confined to reproducing, more or less exactly, Nature, but
the mysterious correspondences which link Nature with
Imagination."Jarocinski 96.
15.
An
attempt to diagram its form as AB A/B (A/B = combination) appears in Richard S.
Parks, The Music of Claude
Debussy. Yale University Press (New Haven and London 1989) 222. Parks
writes, "Another ternary-derived archetype is the tripartite design ...
whose last section synthesizes characteristic features of the first two."
The above AB A/B schema obscures an essential quality of dialectical form: the
progressive generation of B from A and their interaction, so that B gradually
and organically emerges as the antithesis of A.
16.
See
also "Voiles" (Préludes
I #2), where a
whole-tone collection cedes to the emergence of a pentatonic collection).
17.
Pitch-class
E is a member of the whole-tone collection, pitch-class F is a member of the G
major collection, and pitch-class D is shared by both. The figure is meant to
have the sonic value of a sad and frozen landscape: "Ce rhythme doit avoir
la valeur sonore d'un fond du paysage triste et glacé."
18.
In
Example 2 the D minor collection is marked by diamond-shaped noteheads, the
octatonic collection by dotted rectangles and the whole-tone collection by
circles. The G collection is shown in conventional noteheads. Pitch-classes F
and B are shared between the D minor and G collections,
but are not
indicated as such in Figure 1so as to make the emergent processes clearer.
19.
Chromaticism
also plays a constructive role. A half-step source is immediately established
in the ostinato's E F. The half-step idea is further extended in measure 8 and
the near-duplicate 9, accompanied by parallel chromatic minor sevenths B/C to
B/C# in half notes. These are in turn connected by the chromatic trichord F# G
G# in quarter-note motion. Measure 10 - an altered repetition of measure 8 -
presents a chromatic trichord in contrary motion BA A. All this produces an
eleven-member chro-matic set A A B C# D E F F# G G# . The aggregate is
completed by the prelude's first E, in measure 12. (The trichord connection
reappears as C B B in measure 15.) The chromatic process continues in measures
23 to 24. Here, a tetrachord D D E E supports a series of altered dominants.
This leads to a culmination of the chromatic process at measure 26 to 27 where
the trichord G G F supports a series of minor triads as well as a tetrachord D
D C B. These triads, along with the accompanying ostinato form the 11-member
collection E F G G G# A B B C D D. Again, the missing pitch is E, which had
just been heard in the bass motion in measure 24.
20.
Perspectives
of New Music
Spring-Summer 1977.
21.
The
Music of Elliott Carter, David Schiff, Cornell University Press (Ithaca: 1998)
39-40.
22.
George
Perle, Serial Composition
and Atonality. Fourth Edition (U Cal Press: 1977) 94-5.
23.
Greenbaum,
"Stefan Wolpe's Dialectical Logic."
24.
Varèse
- the revolutionary sound surface of his works notwithstanding - was profoundly
influenced by Debussy; this influence is manifest in his brief Un grand sommeil noir
(1906).
25.
Matthew
Greenbaum, "The Proportions of Density 21.5."
26.
"'The
Fantasy Can be Critically Examined': Composition and theory in the thought of
Stefan Wolpe," in Music
Theory and the Exploration of the Past, D. Bernstein & C. Hatch
eds., (U Chicago 1993), 505-524.
27.
Clarkson
507.
28.
Clarkson
520.
29.
in
Elliott Schwartz and Barney Childs, eds., Contemporary
Composers on Contemporary Music (New York, 1967) 274.